Submitted Successfully!
To reward your contribution, here is a gift for you: A free trial for our video production service.
Thank you for your contribution! You can also upload a video entry or images related to this topic.
Version Summary Created by Modification Content Size Created at Operation
1 + 1763 word(s) 1763 2021-07-14 08:24:29 |
2 format correct Meta information modification 1763 2021-10-08 06:13:37 |

Video Upload Options

Do you have a full video?

Confirm

Are you sure to Delete?
Cite
If you have any further questions, please contact Encyclopedia Editorial Office.
Minelli, A. Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines. Encyclopedia. Available online: https://encyclopedia.pub/entry/14839 (accessed on 27 July 2024).
Minelli A. Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines. Encyclopedia. Available at: https://encyclopedia.pub/entry/14839. Accessed July 27, 2024.
Minelli, Alessandro. "Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines" Encyclopedia, https://encyclopedia.pub/entry/14839 (accessed July 27, 2024).
Minelli, A. (2021, October 04). Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines. In Encyclopedia. https://encyclopedia.pub/entry/14839
Minelli, Alessandro. "Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines." Encyclopedia. Web. 04 October, 2021.
Questionable Boundaries between Biological Disciplines
Edit

Recent and ongoing debates in biology and in the philosophy of biology reveal widespread dissatisfaction with the current definitions or circumscriptions, which are often vague or controversial, of key concepts such as the gene, individual, species, and homology, and even of whole disciplinary fields within the life sciences. To some extent, the long growing awareness of these conceptual issues and the contrasting views defended in their regard can be construed as a symptom of the need to revisit traditional unchallenged partitions between the specialist disciplines within the life sciences. I argue here that the current relationships between anchor disciplines (e.g., developmental biology, evolutionary biology, biology of reproduction) and nomadic concepts wandering between them is worth being explored from a reciprocal perspective, by selecting suitable anchor concepts around which disciplinary fields can flexibly move. Two examples are offered: a generalized anchor concept of generation that may suggests new perspectives on development and reproduction) and a species concept as unit of representation of biological diversity that may lead to a taxonomic pluralism to be managed with suitable adjustments of current nomenclature rules.

nomadic concept evolutionary developmental biology interdisciplinary concept transfer

1. Multidisciplinary or Interdisciplinary?

In biology, as in other sciences, interdisciplinarity has been steadily increasing in the last decades, but with a diversity of levels, intensity and outcome. The transfer of concepts, problems, and tools between disciplines is often strongly polarized, with a receiving discipline adopting them from a donating discipline [1], but sometimes this is a two-way affair. In this case we can characterize the process as one of integration, either epistemic or organizational, or both [1]. Moreover, it is an accepted notion that in modern science many key concepts are shared by traditionally separate disciplines, and these are often concepts that do not lend themselves to precise definitions [2].
The biological concepts whose definition has proved more problematic and is still controversial are probably those of species, homology, gene, and individual. In the first case the controversy is particularly strong within the single biological discipline of systematics [3] while affecting also evolutionary biology [4]; in the second case it involves different disciplines (morphology, phylogenetics etc.), mostly insofar as that these are united by the adoption of the comparative method [5]; see [6] for a broader perspective on these cases. The definition of gene has an overt transdisciplinary value, involving genetics in its various declinations, evolutionary biology, developmental biology, and the philosophy of biology [7][8][9][10]; the same applies for the definition of individual [11][12][13][14][15][16].
The need to address seriously, in a flexible and pluralistic way, the problem of a re-determination of the boundaries between biological disciplines is demonstrated by the number of concepts that in recent decades have assumed the value of nomadic concepts [17][18]. This term was proposed to describe concepts for which meaning and domain of application change with the new contexts into which they migrate. This has soon proved true also of the very notion of the nomadic concept [19][20][21]. I argue that the current relationships between anchor disciplines (e.g., developmental biology, evolutionary biology, biology of reproduction) and nomadic concepts wandering between them is worth being explored from a reciprocal perspective, by selecting suitable anchor concepts around which disciplinary fields can flexibly move. Examples could be a generalized anchor concept of generation that may suggest new perspectives on development and reproduction and a species concept as unit of representation of biological diversity that would suggest a taxonomic pluralism requiring suitable adjustments of current nomenclature rules.
It is legitimate to think that the lack of shareable definitions for the terms listed in the penultimate paragraph is not only a consequence of progress in the disciplines in which each of them originated, but also evidence of the disputable delimitation of biological disciplines. Eventually, we must acknowledge the historical specificity of individual disciplines, and possibly also the historical specificity of our own concepts of discipline [22] (p. 51).

2. Hybrid Disciplines—The Case of Evolutionary Developmental Biology

The emergence of a new hybrid discipline may require gross conceptual rearrangements. This happened, in the last two decades of the 20th century, at the interface between evolutionary biology and developmental biology.
Interestingly, these two disciplines had been diverging more and more during most of the century. In the mind of authoritative evolutionary biologists, development was a black box between genotype and phenotype, whose content could be ignored [23]. On the other hand, the transition from the descriptive embryology of the 19th century (which had provided valuable contributions to the understanding of phylogenetic relationships) to the experimental embryology of the following century had seen a progressive loss of interest in the comparative aspects of developmental processes and a growing focus on experimental work restricted to a very small number of model species [24][25]. Eventually, however, formidable technical advances in the second half of the 20th century made it possible to implement a developmental genetics program. One of the most sensational results was the discovery of the involvement of homologous genes in the development of such different organisms as mouse and fruit fly. The increasingly accessible contents of the black box between genotype and phenotype proved to be of utmost interest not only for developmental biology, but also for evolutionary biology. The emergence of a new research field in this interface area is conventionally fixed by two books whose publication dates and titles respectively mark the completion of the maturation phase and the first full expression of the new discipline. In 1983, Rudy Raff and Thomas Kaufman published a book [26], the title of which (Embryos, Genes, and Evolution) clearly identified the subject, approach, and problems of this discipline, while Evolutionary Developmental Biology, the title of the book published nine years later by Brian K. Hall [27], provided the name (often abbreviated as evo-devo) by which the latter was definitively identified [28][29].
Gilbert and Burian’s early summary [30] that evo-devo “is both a synthesis between evolutionary biology and developmental biology and an ongoing negotiation between these two disciplines” (p. 61) is still up-to-date [31]. Winther [32] proposed to characterize evolutionary developmental biology as a trading zone, a catching term introduced by Galison [33] to indicate those interdisciplinary areas in which specific adoption and redefinition of both the concepts and the environment where they are implemented allow successful conceptual transfers [2][21].
For sure, conflicts cannot be avoided even in the best trading zones. In the case of evolutionary developmental biology, Love [34] has pointed to a hardly erasable tension between the two ‘souls’. Repeatability of experimental results requires the highest possible uniformity in the strains (often long inbred laboratory lines) used in the tests. But this choice potentially deletes all the intraspecific variation on which evolution is deemed to happen. In this tug of war between developmental biology and evolutionary biology, it is not surprising that studies effectively coupling developmental genetics and population genetics (devgen-popgen [35]) are still few, despite a few excellent examples such as the already classic studies on the beaks of Darwin’s finches revisited from an evo-devo perspective [36][37]).

3. Beyond Hierarchies and Facile Interdisciplinary Transfers

In these years that witness so much talk about the need to broaden the traditional neo-Darwinian vision of evolution to move towards an extended synthesis [38][39][40] it is necessary, in my opinion, to make an even more generous and adventurous effort and to seek, in an ever wider trading zone, to refresh the relationships between biological disciplines.
An overarching question is the relationship between the disciplinary articulation of the natural sciences and a hierarchical vision of nature structured into levels of organization.
The starting point of a debate that continues to this day [41][42], with an unceasing renewal of points of view and arguments, is a 1958 article by Oppenheim and Putnam [43] postulating both an articulation of nature in terms of levels of organization, and a close reciprocal correspondence between levels of organization in nature and the sciences that describe their components and develop theories on the relationships between them [44]. From these premises, Oppenheim and Putnam derived an entire reductionist program.
A description of reality in terms of levels of organization seemed useful even to those who were ready to recognize that theories are not always “limited to single levels, that levels are always well defined, or that two or more entities can always be unambiguously ordered with respect to level” [45] (p. 215). But in more recent times, the progressive move away from the reductionist program of Oppenheim and Putnam was one of the reasons for the decreasing favor of the very notion of levels of organization [46][47][48], until its total rejection by some authors [49]. Others have brought their arguments against these dismissionary positions, while nevertheless proposing new interpretations (and new epistemic roles) for the notion of organizational levels. While rejecting an ontological interpretation according to which the world would be structured by levels of organization, Brooks and Eronen [50]; see also [51][52] nevertheless save this notion as useful in the abstract description of systems and as a guide in the search for new areas of investigation to be explored. On the other hand, DiFrisco [53][54] rejects the criteria thus far used in identifying organization levels, in terms of compositional relationships or spatial scale, and suggests a dynamic approach that recognizes levels defined on the basis of rates or time scales of processes. Baedke [55] challenges the general acceptance of a never changing existence of levels of organization such as cells, tissues, organs, and individual organisms and points to the necessity of addressing their dynamical nature over developmental time and in evolution.
An overlooked consequence of the generalized acceptance of a vision of the living world in terms of compositional levels organized in part-whole relations [56] is the creation of disciplines through a copy-and-paste process. If in the study of humans and, more generally, of animals, it has proved useful to recognize a science of cells (cytology), a science of tissues (histology), a science of embryonic development (embryology) etc., this disciplinary articulation was accepted as sensible for all animals and even for multicellular organisms at large and corresponding disciplines were created for plants. Many biologists may take for granted, for example, the legitimacy of a plant embryology, but this should be resisted. In plant science, a technical use of the term embryo for the future seedling still enclosed within the seed casings was virtually unknown until 1788, when Gaertner [57] successfully introduced it in his treatise De fructibus et seminibus plantarum (On Plant Fruits and Seeds). Gaertner borrowed a number of terms and concepts from animal embryology. Some of these terms have remained in use for both plants and animals, but nobody would venture today to say, for example, that the placenta of plants is homologous to the placenta of mammals. Unfortunately, instead, the idea of an equivalence between what is called an embryo in either kingdom is still widespread, even among professionals [58].

References

  1. Gerson, E.M. Integration of specialties: An institutional and organizational view. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 2013, 44, 515–524.
  2. Müller, E. Interdisciplinary concepts and their political significance. Contrib. Hist. Concepts 2011, 6, 42–52.
  3. Zachos, F.E. Species Concepts in Biology. Historical Development, Theoretical Foundations and Practical Relevance; Springer: Basel, Switzerland, 2016; ISBN 978-3-3194-4966-1.
  4. Minelli, A.; Fusco, G. Homology. In The Philosophy of Biology: A Companion for Educators; Kampourakis, K., Ed.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2013; pp. 289–322.
  5. Wagner, G.P. Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA; Oxford, UK, 2014; ISBN 9780691156460.
  6. Portin, P.; Wilkins, A. The evolving definition of the term “gene”. Genetics 2017, 205, 1353–1364.
  7. Snyder, M.; Gerstein, M. Defining genes in the genomics era. Science 2003, 300, 258–260.
  8. Griffiths, P.E.; Stotz, K. Genes in the postgenomic era. Theor. Med. Bioeth. 2006, 27, 499–521.
  9. Müller-Wille, S.; Rheinberger, H.-J. Das Gen im Zeitalter der Postgenomik. Eine Wissenschaftshistorische Bestandsaufnahme; Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main, Germany, 2009; ISBN 9783518260258.
  10. Santelices, B. How many kinds of individual are there? Trends Ecol. Evol. 1999, 14, 152–155.
  11. Wilson, J. Biological Individuality: The Identity and Persistence of Living Entities; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999; ISBN 0521624258.
  12. Godfrey-Smith, P. Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2009; ISBN 9780199552047.
  13. Bouchard, F.; Huneman, P. (Eds.) From Groups to Individuals. Evolution and Emerging Individuality; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013; ISBN 9780262018722.
  14. Pradeu, T. Organisms or biological individuals? Combining physiological and evolutionary individuality. Biol. Philos. 2016, 31, 797–817.
  15. Fields, C.; Levin, M. Are planaria individuals? What regenerative biology is telling us about the nature of multicellularity. Evol. Biol. 2018, 45, 237–247.
  16. Stengers, I. (Ed.) D’une Science a L’autre: Des Concepts Nomads; Seuil: Paris, France, 1987; ISBN 8877570180.
  17. Surman, J.; Stráner, K.; Haslinger, P. Nomadic concepts—Biological concepts and their careers beyond biology. Contr. Hist. Concepts 2014, 9, 1–17.
  18. Bal, M. Travelling Concepts in the Humanities: A Rough Guide; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada, 2002; ISBN 0802035299.
  19. Wolfe, C.T. The organism as ontological go-between Hybridity, boundaries and degrees of reality in its conceptual history. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2014, 48, 151–161.
  20. Surman, J.; Stráner, K.; Haslinger, P. Nomadic concepts in the history of biology. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2014, 48, 127–129.
  21. Suárez-Diaz, E. Molecular evolution: Concepts and the origin of disciplines. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2009, 40, 43–53.
  22. Laubichler, M.D. Evolutionary developmental biology offers a significant challenge to the neo-Darwinian paradigm. In Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Biology; Ayala, F., Arp, R., Eds.; Wiley-Blackwell: Malden, MS, USA, 2010; pp. 199–212.
  23. Jenner, R.A. Unburdening evo-devo: Ancestral attractions, model organisms, and basal baloney. Dev. Genes Evol. 2006, 216, 385–394.
  24. Minelli, A.; Baedke, J. Model organisms in evo-devo: Promises and pitfalls of the comparative approach. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 2014, 36, 42–59.
  25. Raff, R.A.; Kaufman, T.C. Embryos, Genes, and Evolution; Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 1983; ISBN 0253206421.
  26. Hall, B.K. Evolutionary Developmental Biology; Chapman & Hall: London, UK, 1992.
  27. Love, A.; Raff, R.A. Knowing your ancestors: Themes in the history of evo-devo. Evol. Dev. 2003, 5, 327–330.
  28. Horder, T.J. A history of evo-devo in Britain. Ann. Hist. Philos. Biol. 2008, 13, 101–174.
  29. Gilbert, S.F.; Burian, R.M. Development, evolution, and evolutionary developmental biology. In Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology; Hall, B.K., Olson, W., Eds.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2003; pp. 61–68.
  30. Baedke, J.; Gilbert, S.F. Evolution and development. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Fall 2020 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Metaphysics Research Lab., Stanford University: Sanford, CA, USA, 2020; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/evolution-development/ (accessed on 7 August 2020).
  31. Winther, R.G. Evo-devo as a trading zone. In Conceptual Change in Biology: Scientific and Philosophical Perspectives on Evolution and Development; Love, A.C., Ed.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2015; pp. 459–482.
  32. Galison, P. Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1997.
  33. Love, A.C. Idealization in evolutionary developmental investigation: A tension between phenotypic plasticity and normal stages. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Biol. Sci. 2010, 365, 679–690.
  34. Abzhanov, A.; Protas, M.; Grant, B.R.; Grant, P.R.; Tabin, C.J. Bmp4 and morphological variation of beaks in Darwin’s finches. Science 2004, 305, 1462–1465.
  35. Abzhanov, A.; Kuo, W.P.; Hartmann, C.; Grant, B.R.; Grant, P.R.; Tabin, C.J. The Calmodulin Pathway and evolution of elongated beak morphology in Darwin’s finches. Nature 2006, 442, 563–567.
  36. Gilbert, S. Evo-devo, devo-evo and devgen-popgen. Biol. Philos. 2003, 18, 347–352.
  37. Pigliucci, M.; Müller, G.B. (Eds.) Evolution: The Extended Synthesis; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2010.
  38. Laland, K.N.; Uller, T.; Feldman, M.; Sterelny, K.; Müller, G.B.; Moczek, A.; Jabonka, E.; Odling-Smee, J. Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Yes, urgently. Nature 2014, 514, 161–164.
  39. Laland, K.N.; Uller, T.; Feldman, M.; Sterelny, K.; Müller, G.B.; Moczek, A.; Jabonka, E.; Odling-Smee, J. The extended evolutionary synthesis: Its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B 2015, 282, 20151019.
  40. Eronen, M.I.; Brooks, D.S. Levels of organization in biology. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2018 ed.; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/levels-org-biology/ (accessed on 9 August 2020).
  41. Brooks, D.S.; DiFrisco, J.; Wimsatt, W.C. (Eds.) Introduction. In Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, forthcoming.
  42. Oppenheim, P.; Putnam, H. Unity of science as a working hypothesis. In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science; Feigl, H., Maxwell, G., Scriven, M., Eds.; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 1958; pp. 3–36.
  43. Brigandt, I. Beyond reduction and pluralism: Toward an epistemology of explanatory integration in biology. Erkenntnis 2010, 73, 295–311.
  44. Wimsatt, W.C. Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In Consciousness and the Brain. A Scientific and Philosophical Enquiry; Globus, G.G., Maxwell, G., Savodnik, I., Eds.; Plenum: New York, NY, USA, 1976; pp. 205–267.
  45. Eronen, M.I. Levels of organization: A deflationary account. Biol. Philos. 2015, 30, 39–58.
  46. Eronen, M.I. No levels, no problems: Downward causation in neuroscience. Philos. Sci. 2013, 80, 1042–1052.
  47. Potochnik, A.; McGill, B. The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philos. Sci. 2012, 79, 120–140.
  48. Thalos, M. Without Hierarchy: The Scale Freedom of the Universe; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013.
  49. Brooks, D.S.; Eronen, M.I. The significance of levels of organization for scientific research: A heuristic approach. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 2018, 68–69, 34–41.
  50. Brooks, D.S. A new look at ‘levels of organization’ in biology. Erkenntnis 2019.
  51. Brooks, D.S. In defense of levels: Layer cakes and guilt by association. Biol. Theory 2017, 12, 142–156.
  52. DiFrisco, J. Time scales and levels of organization. Erkenntnis 2017, 82, 795–818.
  53. DiFrisco, J. Integrating composition and process in levels of developmental evolution. In Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences; Brooks, D.S., DiFrisco, J., Wimsatt, W.C., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, forthcoming.
  54. Baedke, J. The origin of new levels of organization. In Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences; Brooks, D., DiFrisco, J., Wimsatt, W., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, forthcoming.
  55. Wimsatt, W.C. Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations to Reality; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007; ISBN 9780674015456.
  56. Gaertner, J. De Fructibus et Seminibus Plantarum; Typis Academiae Carolinae: Stutgardia, Germany, 1788.
  57. Minelli, A. Understanding Development; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, forthcoming.
More
Information
Contributor MDPI registered users' name will be linked to their SciProfiles pages. To register with us, please refer to https://encyclopedia.pub/register :
View Times: 451
Revisions: 2 times (View History)
Update Date: 08 Oct 2021
1000/1000
Video Production Service